Defining art is a task that is both necessary yet
inextricably complex. Regarding the former, a definition necessarily functions
to dissociate art objects and non-art objects from one another. Defining an
entity as “art” is a judgment which essentializes an object or concept into an
elementary, binary classification that acts as a foundation to further attempt
many meanings that could articulate a definition. This is to say, that to
understand what art is, one also needs to understand what it is not. Although, in that there is no general consensus as to what art is, defining art comes to be a
subjective matter which designates any definitive meaning to be uniquely
particular and thus difficult to equate to a far-reaching generalization. In
this sense, any definition of art will always be permeable, intangible, and
indefinite. Thus, “art” is a word with abounding definitions that cannot be
definitively fixed in the same way, for example, that the definition of the
word “shovel” can be reasonably established. Any definition of “art” can be
applied essentially or particularly, and subsequently disputed. Anything can be
defined as “art,” yet justifying the definition can be problematic and
ultimately unsatisfactory. Therefore, the question of definition means that art
is both a classification that is easily administered as well as something that
is paradoxically ineffable. However, the contentiousness of the question itself
elicits its importance.
The importance of defining art has led to a profusion of
theories to support particular definitions throughout recorded history. Art has
been variously defined as human-made objects or concepts that imitate natural
phenomena, communicate information, express emotion, or prompt interpretation
to find a meaning in such a way that distinguishes an object, characteristic,
or concept from a non-art object, characteristic, or concept. In this fashion,
the only essential quality to art is the word, “art.” Thus, theories of art
have emerged that are cognizant of this difficulty and have accordingly
developed principles that attempt to explain the meaning in and of art. The efforts of all the theoretical pursuits indicate
the significance of art’s meaning and have contributed to a body of knowledge
that is comprised of many definitions. Clearly, the existence of art theory
correlates to a value in seeking to understand what art is and is not. Yet, as to
the importance of defining art, the value lies in the question and not
definitive answers. There is more value in pursuing an answer with a diversity
of questions than arriving at an answer, because questions produce new and
divergent ways of understanding a complex concept like art that do not
necessarily define art. Consequently, endeavoring to define art is distinctly
important, whereas an ultimate definition is less important.
Two strategies emerged in the 20th century to
accommodate the radical changes in art and its appreciation. The first derived
from the Frankfurt School with the theories of Walter Benjamin and Theodor Adorno.
This approach argued that art should be understood within the economic and
cultural conditions of modern capitalism. The second strategy developed from
the theories of Arthur Danto and George Dickie which placed the meaning of an
artwork outside the work itself. This approach argued that an artwork’s
efficacy as art was no longer inherent to the work of art itself. These two
strategies thoroughly altered the way in which art is understood and
accordingly provide insight into the question of “what art is.”
In his 1935 essay, “The Work of Art in the Age of Mechanical
Reproduction,” Walter Benjamin addresses the ways in which mass reproduction of
aesthetic works alters the experience and perception of art. However, it is
noted that art changes along with cultural changes, and thus functions as a
means in which to perceive and understand the wider world. Benjamin writes,
“During long periods of history, the mode of human sense perception changes
with humanity’s entire mode of existence.” Demonstrating this process, Benjamin
uses the term, “aura” to describe the authenticity of an original artwork that
is established by way of a ritualistic basis. In this sense, the aura is
associated to the cultural context in which the artwork was created. It has a
provincial cult value in its extrinsic properties that exist as a part of the
aura. With the standardization of mass produced and reproduced artworks, the
aura has been disassociated from the work. The original work is now removed
from experience, or there is no original at all in the sense that the artwork
is designed for mass production, as with the mediums of photography and film.
Nonetheless, Benjamin recognizes that these technological adaptations have the
means to positively alter the ways in which art is created and appreciated. As
a result of this paradigmatic shift, traditions are curbed by experimentation,
and art can be widely appreciated through its new availability that can foster
conditions for social and political change. Benjamin views these changes as an
expansion of the definition and function of art.
Theodor Adorno, in his in his 1967 essay, “Is Art
Lighthearted?” focuses on art’s connection to society. Whereas mass production
can inspire new ways of understanding art in Benjamin’s perspective, Adorno
views mass production as a symptom of capitalism that further displaces
individual freedom. Thus, the effects of capitalism suppress “high” or serious
art, and substitute readily available, low-quality entertainment for art’s
genuine function. This function is liberatory in the sense that the beauty and
complexity of art allows for a freedom of consciousness apart from the
conditions of reality. Adorno claims that the liberatory value of art is that
“it embodies something like freedom in the midst of unfreedom.” This
“unfreedom” cultivates various cultural mechanisms, such as entertainment or
what Adorno and Max Horkheimer term the “culture industry,” that function to
subjugate individual and social freedoms with dull, satiating amusements.
Consequently, Adorno advocates for a renewal in artistic originality that moves
beyond mind-numbing entertainment, as well as the seriousness and gravity of
the human condition, as exemplified in his statement; “it is not possible to
write poetry after Auschwitz.” This new artistic originality would uniquely
speak to the distinctiveness of human nature in a way that is transcendent of
the conditions of reality.
In a wholly different approach from that of Adorno and
Benjamin, Arthur Danto emphasizes the importance of theoretical perspectives to
inform conceptions of art. In this perspective, documented in his 1964 essay
“The Artworld,” works of art are components of a larger “artworld” that
ultimately determine art’s status as art. That is to say, it is the context as
established by a theory of art that accounts for the aesthetic efficacy of an
artwork. In this fashion, the evocative capabilities of a work of art exist
outside the object itself and are instead realized conceptually. Danto’s
“artworld” is a contextual atmosphere that is informed by theories that account
for cultural developments. He proclaims; “To see something as art requires
something the eye cannot decry – an atmosphere of artistic theory, a knowledge
of the history of art: an artworld.” Hence, theories of art expand the meaning
of art even though the work of art itself undergoes no transformation. The
cultural zeitgeist creates the conditions for specific art, insofar as the
artist understands the time and place in which their work will be understood as
something evocative of a specific cultural meaning. Citing Andy Warhol’s Brillo Box as an exemplary of his
theory, Danto affirms “It could not have been art fifty years ago. But then
there could not have been, everything being equal, flight insurance in the
Middle Ages, or Etruscan typewriter erasers. The world has to be ready for
certain things, the artworld no less than the real one.” To this extent,
Danto’s theory substantially broadens the explanation of what art is.
In 1984, George Dickie wrote, “The New Institutional Theory
of Art” in which he attaches an institutional system to the success or failure
of a work of art. Dickie’s theory claims that the overall meaning of an artwork
is participatory, in that an artist creates a specific artwork for a specific
public, and that this combination entails an institutional network. These
institutional factors conceptually formulate the manner in which an art object
is determined to be art. This is to say, that an artist produces an artifact
that is then received by a knowledgeable institutional public, which may
consist of aficionados, scholars, critics, and curators, that then confer the
artifact as art. Defining art as art is a classificatory matter, wherein the
institutional framework of artist and informed public define art. In this
sense, a definition of art is particular to a category, whereas outside of the
category the same definition would not be understandable or acceptable as art.
Dickie’s theory increases ways in which art can be understood as art, and
therefore allows for more definitions of art.
No comments:
Post a Comment